Wednesday, June 07, 2023

The Fundamental Argument for Dispositionalism about Belief

I'm back from travel to Paris and Antwerp, where I spoke with people influenced by, and critical of, my "dispositionalist" approach to belief.  A critique of my work has also just appeared in the journal Theoria.  It's an honor to be criticized!

Over the years, I've advanced various arguments for dispositionalism about belief (here, here, here, here, here, here, here).  Today, I want to synthesize and restate the most fundamental one.

Dispositionalism Characterized

According to dispositionalism as I understand it, to believe some proposition P is nothing more or less than to have a certain suite of behavioral, cognitive, and phenomenal (that is, conscious experience involving) dispositions.  Which dispositions?  Dispositions of the sort that we are apt to associate with belief that P.  This might sound circular, but it's not: It is to ground metaphysics in commonsense psychology.  Stealing an example from Gilbert Ryle, to believe that the ice is dangerously thin is to be prone to skate warily, to dwell in the imagination on possible disasters, to warn other skaters, to agree with other people's assertions to that effect, to feel alarm and surprise upon seeing someone skate successfully across it, and so on, including being ready generally to make plans and draw consequences that depend on the truth of P.

[Midjourney rendition of skaters approaching thin ice]

As is typical of dispositions in general, the relevant dispositions hold only ceteris paribus (all else being equal or normal or right).  For example, you might not be disposed to warn other skaters if you'd like to see them fall in.  The dispositions are potentially limitless in number: Less obvious ones include the disposition to assume that a circular disk cut from the ice would be fragile and the disposition to attend curiously to a fox walking across the ice.  One needn't possess every disposition on the infinitely expandable list in order to count as a P believer -- just enough of the dispositional structure that attributing the belief to you adequately captures your general cognitive posture toward P.

Although dispositionalism about belief can seem confusing, dispositionalism about personality traits is intuitive.  Thus, comparison to personality traits is instructive.  Consider extraversion.  To be an extravert is nothing more or less than to have the dispositional profile stereotypical of extraversion: a tendency to say yes to party invitations, a tendency to enjoy meeting new people, a readiness to take the lead in conversation and in organizing social events, and so forth.  Of course all of these dispositions are ceteris paribus and no one is going to to be 100% extraverted down the line.  Match the dispositional characterization of extraversion closely enough, and you're an extravert; that's all there is to it.  Similarly, match the dispositional characterization of being a thin-ice believer closely enough, and you are one; that's all there is to it.

The Fundamental Argument

Now consider some alternative, non-dispositionalist account of belief, where believing is constituted by some feature other than one's overall dispositional profile with respect to P.  Call that alternative feature Feature X.  Maybe Feature X is having a stored representation with the content that P.  Maybe Feature X is having a particular neural structure.  Maybe Feature X involves being responsive to evidence for or against P.  If Feature X is metaphysically distinct from having a belief-that-P-ish dispositional structure, then it ought to be possible in principle to imagine cases in which Feature X is absent and the dispositional structure is present and vice versa.  I submit that in such cases, first, we intuitively do, and second, we pragmatically ought, to attribute belief in a way that tracks the belief-that-P-ish dispositional structure rather than the presence or absence of Feature X.  That's the fundamental argument.

As a warm-up, consider space aliens.  Tomorrow, they arrive from Alpha Centauri.  They learn our languages, trade with us, fall in love with some of us, join our corporations and governments, write philosophy and psychology articles, reveal their technological secrets, and recount amazing tales about their home planet.  Stipulate, too, that we somehow know their cognitive dispositions and their phenomenology (that is, their streams of conscious experience).  We know that if they say "P is so, I'm sure of it!" and then not-P is revealed to be true, they normally feel surprise.  We know that they have inner speech and imagery like ours, and that when they assert that P they tend to draw further logical conclusions from P and make plans that will only work if P is true.

I submit that if we know all these dispositional facts about the aliens, we know that they have beliefs.  What kinds of brains do they have?  What kind of underlying cognitive architecture?  How did they come to have their present dispositional structures?  Who knows!  As far as belief is concerned, it doesn't matter.  They have what it takes to believe.

Suppose that Feature X is having internal structured representations of a certain sort.  Imagine, now, a space alien -- call her Breana -- with a radically different cognitive architecture from ours, lacking internal structured representations of the required sort, but possessing the behavioral, cognitive, and phenomenal dispositions characteristic of belief.  Breana will act and react, behaviorally, emotionally, and cognitively, just like an entity with beliefs.  Maybe Breana says "microbes live beneath the ice of Europa" with a feeling of sincerity and accompanying visual imagery of slime beneath the ice.  She draws relevant conclusions (Earth is not the only planet with life in the Solar System).  She would feel confused and surprised if a seemingly knowledgeable friend contradicted her.  If a human asked where we should probe to find alien life, she would recommend Europa.  And so on.  Breana believes, despite lacking internal structured representations of the required sort.

My opponent might say that if Breana acts and reacts as I have described her, then she must have internal representations of the required sort and thus would not be a counterinstance to a representationalist account.  I respond with a dilemma: Either representationalism does not commit to the existence of internal representations of the required sort whenever the belief-that-P-ish dispositional structure is present or it does commit.  If the former, then we ought to be able to construct a Breana-like case without the required underlying representations, producing the objectionable case of the previous paragraph.  If the latter -- that is, if it is metaphysically or conceptually necessary that whenever a belief-that-P-ish dispositional structure is present, the entity has the required representational structure -- then the so-called "representationalism" collapses into dispositionalism: The dispositions drive the metaphysical car, so to speak, and having the pattern of dispositions is just what it is to represent.

How about the converse case, where the representational structure is present but the dispositions are absent?  Breana has a stored representation with the content P, but she has no inclination to act or react, or to reason or plan, accordingly.  "Microbes live beneath the ice in Europa" is somehow internally represented, but she would not assent to that proposition verbally or in inner speech; she would feel no surprise upon learning that it is false; she would never make any plans contingent upon its truth; when she imagines Europa, she pictures it as sterile; if quizzed on the topic, she would fail; in no condition could she be provoked to remember that she learned this; and so on.  Breana will of course sincerely deny that she believes P.  It would be strange to insist that despite her sincere protests, she really does believe.

Thus, to the extent that representationalism's Feature X comes apart from dispositional structure, our intuitive standards of belief attribution follow the dispositional structure rather than the presence or absence of Feature X.  And that's how it should be.  What we can and do care about in belief attribution is the believer's overall cognitive posture toward the world -- how they are disposed to act and react, what they will affirm and depend on, what they take for granted in their inferences, and so forth -- not whether there's a tokening of "P" in a hidden mental warehouse.

Note that unlike old-school behaviorist dispositionalism, this argument is immune to concerns about puppets and play-acting.  (Actually, I think the behaviorist has some underappreciated resources here, but dispositionalism of the form I prefer need not rely on those resources.)  Puppets aren't conscious and don't reason, so they have no phenomenal or cognitive dispositions.  Actors who pretend to believe that P while really holding not-P have the phenomenal and cognitive dispositions characteristic of not-P, including relying on not-P in their own deceptive plans, and the ceteris paribus clause is triggered for their behavioral dispositions, explaining why they don't act like P believers.  (Compare: An extravert paid a large sum to act like an introvert is really still an extravert.)

Other approaches to belief are vulnerable to the same fundamental argument.  Suppose that Feature X involves the capacity to rationally revise your belief in the face of counterevidence.  Now imagine someone who acts and reacts exactly like a P-believer, matching the dispositional profile in every respect, except that they stubbornly eschew any counterevidence.  We ordinarily would, and should, describe that person as a P-believer.  They will self-ascribe the belief, insist on its truth, reason from it, plan on its basis, and so forth.  Of course they believe it!  In fact, if they would never revise it, we might be inclined to say they believe it very strongly indeed.

Suppose that Feature X involves something about the causal history of the belief state: To be a belief, the cognitive state must have been caused in a certain way.  Now imagine Swampman: Lightning strikes a swamp, and by freak quantum chance a molecule-for-molecule duplicate of your favorite philosopher emerges.  Let's stipulate (though it's complicated) that this philosopher has all the dispositions characteristic of belief.  We would, and should, say that Swampman believes.  Or imagine a conscious robot, printed fresh from the factory with a full set of behavioral, cognitive, and phenomenal dispositions.  This robot believes, even though the disposition, for example, to say "Earth is approximately spherical" did not arise in the usual way from evidence or testimony to that effect.  Again, this seems both natural to say and to track what we do and should care about in ascribing beliefs. 

Suppose that Feature X involves a normative standard.  A belief is a state that is "correct" only if it is true.  Either assessibility by this standard corresponds with having the required dispositional structure, or assessibility by this standard can come apart from having the required dispositional structure.  If the former, then being assessible by the normative standard is a consequence of having the dispositional structure constitutive of believing.  If the latter, then either there are beliefs that are not normatively assessible in that way (e.g., religious beliefs?) or there are states that are normatively assessible in the way we normally assess beliefs but which are not in fact beliefs (e.g., delusions?).

The Metaphilosophical Frame

Although I think alternative views often face empirical problems (especially concerning "in-between" cases of belief in which people only approximately match the relevant dispositional profiles), the fundamental argument as I've described it here doesn't rely on empirical objections to alternative views.  Instead, it relies on a particular metaphilosophical approach.

Stipulate that we can define "belief" in a dispositionalist way or alternatively in some other way, and that both definitions are coherent and face no insuperable empirical obstacles.  Now we, as philosophers, face a choice.  How do we want to define belief?  What definition captures what we do care about and should care about in belief ascription?  What way of thinking about belief sorts cases in the way it's most useful to sort them?

We will ordinarily, I think, find it natural and intuitive to sort cases by the dispositionalist criteria.  That creates a default supposition in favor of dispositionalism.  But dispositionalism might not always track ordinary patterns of belief ascription.  In some cases, our intuitions are ambivalent or go the other way.  (See my discussion of intellectualism, for example.)  More important, the dispositionalist approach tracks what matters in belief ascription.  Dispositionalism captures what we should most want to capture with the term "belief" -- that is, our general dispositional posture toward the truth of P, whether we will affirm it, defend it, rely on it in planning and inference, feel confident when we contemplate it, and so forth.

11 comments:

Howie said...

How about belief in God? What behavior would God believing behavior consist of?

Arnold said...

The cart before the horse: "It is to ground metaphysics in commonsense psychology."...

...Isn't it today to say: 'To ground psychology in metaphysics' common sense', for what is in front of oneself at any moment...

"As is typical of dispositions in general, the relevant dispositions hold only ceteris paribus (all else being equal or normal or right)."...and...

"Now we, as philosophers, face a choice. How do we want to define belief? What definition captures what we do care about and should care about in belief ascription? What way of thinking about belief sorts cases in the way it's most useful to sort them?"...thanks...

But what do you mean, in this post, by metaphysics...

chinaphil said...

Huh... I feel like I'm pretty sympathetic to dispositionalism, and yet most of these arguments didn't work for me!
The objections, briefly would be:
Beliefs are like character traits: there's a big difference, which is that the list of character traits is finite, and in fact very small. I think I can only list a couple of dozen distinguishable character traits. Whereas beliefs seem to map out a very different space - infinite in its variation.
The space aliens turn out not to have feature X: this doesn't seem to me to be how we think at all. We might start out thinking that dolphins are fish, then discover they have feature X that makes them mammals. We don't then turn around and say, "No, all those reasons they seemed like fish still hold, therefore we must continue to classify them as fish." Instead we develop a new and deeper understanding: they share some features with fish (live in the sea) and some with mammals (breathe air and live young), and in fact historically evolved from other mammals. I don't see why we'd be forced into a choose-one-or-the-other situation.
The representationalists commit/don't commit: This argument cuts both ways. If representationalists commit to the belief that representations and only representations can cause belief-dispositions, then yes, representationalism collapses into dispositionalism, but by exactly the same token, dispositionalism collapses into representationalism.
The representational structure is present but the dispositions are absent: This one bites a bit, because that's exactly the situation we're in with AI. They have representations coming out of their ears, but don't seem to have dispositions, and I don't feel inclined to say they have beliefs. I think a representationalist would have to say here that what AIs are missing is consistency of belief: they have all the representations of P and not-P, and they don't make much effort to let any P drive out any not-P. Belief does seem to involve the exclusion of not-P as much as it does the affirmation of P... I'm not sure about this yet.
We don't care about tokening of P in the warehouse: Yes, I agree with this, but I think it's not relevant because in general, we have all the tokens (a bit like AIs do). Believing P is more about denying not-P than it is about possessing P. So the question is, do we deny not-P in our mental warehouse, and we do care very much about that. Drunk drivers all contain "don't drink and drive" in their mental warehouse. The problem is that (many of them) believe "drinking doesn't materially affect my ability to drive safely," which means they deny a bunch of tokens like, "I am much more likely to crash after two drinks," "I cannot accurately judge my speed after two drinks," etc. Education often works specifically on those denials, as a route to getting at the core belief about their own ability to drive after drinking.
Ability to revise evidence: Actually, if someone never revises their beliefs, often we explicitly separate those beliefs out and give them another label: prejudices, assumptions, faith, psychological tic...
Swampman: Argument from magic, in general this category can be rejected. Even when Chalmers uses them, haha!
Normative standard: I haven't understood this argument yet, will come back to it.

So... yeah, interesting that these aren't working for me, even though dispositionalism seems intuitively right in many ways. They did help me to see a little more clearly that I think beliefs must be in large part about the denial of not-P. I think we have lots of ideas, but they only become beliefs when we start denying the contradictions...
Thanks, it's a beautifully clear write-up, as ever.

Eric Schwitzgebel said...

Thanks for the comments, folks!

@ Howie: For starters, affirming that God exists, following the precepts of the religion (or feeling guilty if one doesn't), identifying as a member of that religious group.

@ Arnold: By metaphysics, I mean the study of the fundamental nature of things.

@ chinaphil: Ah, the worst news! Someone sympathetic with the view who thinks the arguments don't work. Partial responses:

* On character traits: I think there are infinitely many of these too, if we're liberal (as we should be) about what counts as a character trait, e.g., being the type of person who rocks out to music while driving, being grumpy specifically about political disagreements, liking to have a consistent morning routine. If we don't want to think of these as "character traits" in the "Big 5" sense, still they are *something* -- an ontological type that fits in broadly with "character" or "personality".

* On space aliens: We *could* go for the "deep" explanation. My prediction is that we won't and shouldn't. I like John Dupre on this issue. We could have decided to keep calling whales fish, but we decided not to; and for "fruit" and "butterflies" we stick with the folk categories despite their not being cladistically sound by the usual standards of scientific biology. There are many and conflicting reasons for classification decisions and internal structure doesn't and shouldn't always win.

* On rep/disp collapse: That's a representationalism so weak that even a dispositionalist could love it. I don't mind at all saying that to represent just is to be prone to act and think in certain ways.

* On drunk driving, etc., I'm fine with allowing complex representational structure underneath (though I think it is often given a cartoonish rather than realistic gloss); what matters is how that undergirds the dispositional structure in general, and with conflicting/inconsistent representations one tends to get in-between cases.

Howard said...

I doubt those things can be easily operationalized. There are people who go to church who have their doubts, for instance. I think this area like romantic love, has its ambivalences. Maybe even from a godlike view, these things cannot be pinned down. There are some kind of beliefs hard to pin down and hard to be marked by behavior. You'd have to conduct case studies to convince me

Mike Roche said...

Dispositionalism: believing that P is constituted by one’s overall dispositional profile with respect to P.

Alternatives to dispositionalism: believing that P is constituted by Feature X (e.g., having a stored representation that P; having the capacity to rationally revise your belief in the face of counterevidence; having the right causal or historical profile; etc.).

My reconstruction of the argument for dispositionalism: Feature X is either (i) metaphysically or conceptually tied to having the right overall dispositional profile with respect to P, or (ii) it is not.

Horn 2: if (ii), then cases can be constructed where Feature X is present in the absence of the relevant dispositional profile, or cases can be constructed where the relevant dispositional profile is present in the absence of Feature X.

In such cases, it is most plausible to side with dispositionalism. It would be a mistake to ascribe a belief that p to a person who lacks the right dispositional profile with respect to P, and it would be a mistake to not ascribe a belief that p to a person who possesses the right dispositional profile with respect to P.

Horn 1: if (i), then cases of the kind just mentioned cannot be constructed. However, it will be most plausible that Feature X is metaphysically or conceptually dependent on the dispositional profile.

This is a very interesting argument! (Though I don’t know whether Eric would agree that it is an accurate reconstruction of his own.) However, it’s difficult to know in the abstract whether it works. It seems that the particular value for Feature X matters.

When Feature X = having a stored representation, then we probably land on Horn 1 and I think the argument there is plausible: “The dispositions drive the metaphysical car, so to speak, and having the pattern of dispositions is just what it is to represent.”

When Feature X = having the right causal or historical profile, then we probably land on Horn 2 and I think the argument there is plausible: “Let's stipulate (though it's complicated) that this philosopher has all the dispositions characteristic of belief. We would, and should, say that Swampman believes.”

But perhaps there’s a value for Feature X such that we land on Horn 1 but the argument there is not compelling when applied to Feature X. Or perhaps there's a value for Feature X such that we land on Horn 2 but the argument there is not compelling when applied to Feature X. (FWIW, I suspect the first of these possibilities is more likely.)

I wonder if there’s a way to argue independently of the particular value for Feature X that if Feature X is metaphysically or conceptually tied to having the right overall dispositional profile with respect to P, then it is most plausible that Feature X is metaphysically or conceptually dependent on the dispositional profile.

Arnold said...

You have hit some well grounded sounding notes...
...Is the 'fundamental nature of things'...work...

Biblically out of Eden and Traditionally in Family...
...from then till now, being alive is dispositional...

What is work...learning to let beliefs go...

In the Theoria critique, I could not find any direct mention of metaphysics...

Eric Schwitzgebel said...

Thanks for the continuing comments, folks!

Mike: Yes, that's a good reconstruction. On your last point: Right, "tied to" and "dependent" are not quite the same, so there's potentially room to argue that when the dispositions and Feature X would always co-occur, Feature X rather than the dispositions is the property in virtue of which the person believes. However, I'm very liberal about metaphysical necessity, inclining to think it collapses into conceptual necessity, so I'm not sure we can even construct such cases without simply doing so by restating the concept of a dispositional profile in different words.

Paul D. Van Pelt said...

I know (I think) what dispositional means. Disposition refers to temperament. And that attribute or detriment colors how we think, speak,read, write and behave on numerous issues. Thinkers have contended with such issues for centuries. Philosophers have built reputations; scientists and mathematicians have made friends; solidified animosities...the Church reveled in the latter. It gave impetus to pursuit of redemption and salvation, essentially, reason for the Church to BE. It don't get any better than that. I have asserted that some philosophers were sufferers...not good for dispositions. There are probably ten-fold more than I have considered. Were they all crazy? No, they merely suffered. For better, or not,adversity is as likely to spawn creativity and/or genius as its' opposite. This is what we do, for Christ's sake! It is not rocket science. It is not even philosophy, IMHO.

David Duffy said...

I too don't think the analogy from personality to atomic/specific beliefs offers much. The question of few versus many personality dimensions is an old mathematical one about factor analysis - viz first order and second order personality factors. The Eysenckian factors are first order and uncorrelated with each other, and are supposedly trying to summarize broad characteristics of human and non-human nervous systems. I might try and characterize these as different weighting of the value of different stimuli eg characterization of environmental features as more or less threatening to bodily integrity (Eysenckian "neuroticism"). We can see these as affecting belief - Eysenck was interested in political conservatism as risk-averseness, but not the fine detail of a particular belief (eg "pyjama parties are bad", one item of the Wilson-Patterson conservatism scale ;)). And consider adverse moral judgements as disgust...

Howie said...

Hi Eric

Let me offer you my first impression of your argument for dispositionalism
It seems reductionist. People who believe in God go to church, but some people who go to church (or synagogue or Mosques) do not believe in God or are ambivalent
Or take the man who shot Neely who was a homeless man in the subway. His motivations are underdetermined. He could have had the belief that homeless people are subhuman or he could have had the belief that people who are violent ought to be attacked or that he himself had a special role as a Marine to avenge or protect innocent people
I suspect you have an answer, which is why I ask, and as far as I know I am no philosopher and I suspect your interlocutors in Europe may have raised similar objections, so I raise my objections