Wednesday, October 30, 2024

The Ethics of Harmonizing with the Dao

Reading the ancient Chinese philosophers Xunzi and Zhuangzi, I am inspired to articulate an ethics of harmonizing with the dao (the "way"). This ethics doesn't quite map onto any of the three conceptualizations of ethics that are standard in Western philosophy (consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics), nor is it exactly a "role ethics" of the sort sometimes attributed to ancient Confucians.

Xunzi

The ancient Confucian Xunzi articulates a vision of the world in which Heaven, Earth, and humanity operate in harmony:

Heaven has its proper seasons,
Earth has its proper resources,
And humankind has its proper order,
-- this is called being able to form a triad
(Ch 17, l. 34-37; Hutton trans. 2014, p. 176).

Heaven (tian, literally the sky, but with strong religious associations) and Earth are jointly responsible for what we might now call the "laws of nature" and all "natural" phenomena -- including, for example, the turning of the seasons, the patterns of wind and rain, the tendency for plants and animals to thrive under certain conditions and wither under other conditions. Also belonging to these natural phenomena are the raw materials with which humans work: not only the raw materials of wood, metal, and fiber, but also the raw material of natural human inclinations: our tendency to enjoy delicious tastes, our tendency to react angrily to provocations, our general preference for kin over strangers.

Xunzi views humanity's task as creating the third corner of a triad with Heaven and Earth by inventing customs and standards of proper behavior that allow us to harmonize with Heaven and Earth, and with each other. For example, through trial and error, our ancestors learned the proper times and methods for sowing and reaping, how to regulate flooding rivers, how to sharpen steel and straighten wood, how to make pots that won't leak, how to make houses that won't fall over, and so on. Our ancestors also -- again through trial and error -- learned the proper rituals and customs and standards of behavior that permit people to coexist harmoniously with each other without chaotic conflict, without excessive or inappropriate emotions, and with an allocation of goods that allow all to flourish according to their status and social role.

Following the dao can be conceptualized for Xunzi, then, as aligning harmoniously into this triad. Abide by the customs and standards of behavior that contribute to the harmonious whole, in which crops are properly planted, towns are properly constructed, the crafts flourish, and humans thrive in an orderly society.

Each of us has a different role, in accord with the proper customs of a well-ordered society: the barley farmer has one role, the soldier another role, the noblewoman yet another, the traveling merchant yet another. It's not unreasonable to view Xunzi's ethics as a kind of role ethics, according to which the fundamental moral principle is that one adheres to one's proper role in society. It's also not unreasonable to think of the customs and standards of proper behavior as a set of rules to which one ought to adhere (those rules applying in different ways according to one's position in society), and thus to view Xunzi's ethics as a kind of deontological (rule-based) ethics. However, there might also be room to interpret harmonious alignment with the dao as the most fundamental feature of ethical behavior. Adherence to one's role and to the proper traditional customs and practices, on this interpretation of Xunzi, would be only derivatively good, because doing so typically constitutes harmonious alignment.

A test case is to imagine, through Xunzi's eyes, whether a morally well-developed sage might be ethically correct sometimes to act contrary to their role and to the best traditional standards of good behavior, if they correctly see that by doing so they contribute better to the overall harmony of Heaven, Earth, and humankind. I'm tempted to think that Xunzi would indeed permit this -- though only very cautiously, since he is pessimistic about the moral wisdom of ordinary people -- and thus that for him harmonious alignment with the dao is more fundamental than roles and rules. However, I'm not sure I can find direct textual support in favor of this interpretation; it's possible I'm being overly "charitable".

[image source]

A Zhuangzian Correction

A Xunzian ethics of this sort is, I think, somewhat attractive. But it is also deeply traditionalist and conformist in a way I find unappealing. It could use a Zhuangzian twist -- and the idea of "harmonizing with the dao" is at least as Zhuangzian (and "Daoist") as it is Confucian.

Zhuangzi imagines a wilder, more wondrous cosmos than Xunzi's neatly ordered triad of Heaven, Earth, and humankind -- symbolized (though it's disputable how literally) by people so enlightened that they can walk without touching the ground; trees that count 8000 years as a single autumn; gracious emperors with no eyes, ears, nose, or mouth; people with skin like frost who live by drinking dew; enormous, useless trees who speak to us in dreams; and more. This is the dao, wild beyond human comprehension, with which Zhuangzi aims to harmonize.

There are, I think, in Zhuangzi's picture -- though he would resist any effort to fully capture it in words -- ways of flowing harmoniously along with this wondrous and incomprehensible dao and ways of straining unproductively against it. One can be easygoing and open-minded, welcome surprise and difference, not insist on jamming everything into preconceived frames and plans; and one can contribute to the delightful weirdness of the world in one's own unique way. This is Zhuangzian harmony. You become a part of a world that is richer and more wondrous because it contains you, while allowing other wonderful things to also naturally unfold.

In a radical reading of Zhuangzi, ethical obligations and social roles fall away completely. There is little talk in Zhuangzi's Inner Chapters, for example, of our obligation to support others. I don't know that we have to read Zhuangzi radically; but regardless of that question of interpretation, I suggest that there's an attractive middle between Xunzi's conventionalism and Zhuangzi's wildness. Each can serve as a corrective to the other.

In the ethical picture that emerges from this compromise, we each contribute uniquely to a semi-ordered cosmos, participating in social harmony, but not rigidly -- also transcending that harmony, breaking rules and traditions for the better, making the world richer and more wondrous, each in our diverse ways, while also supporting others who contribute in their different ways, whether those others are human, animal, plant, or natural phenomena.

Contrasts

This is not a consequentialist ethics: It is not that our actions are evaluated in terms of the good or bad consequences they have (and still less that the actions are evaluated by a summation of the good minus the bad consequences). Instead, harmonizing with the dao is to participate in something grand, without need of a further objective. Like the deontologist, Xunzi and Zhuangzi and my imagined compromise philosopher needn't think that right or harmonious action will always have good long-term results. Nor is it a deontological or role ethics: There is no set of rules one must always follow or some role one must always adhere to. Nor is it a virtue ethics: There is no set of virtues to which we all must aspire or a distinctive pattern of human flourishing that constitutes the highest attainment. We each contribute in different ways -- and if some virtues often prove to be important, they are derivatively important in the same way that rules and roles can be derivatively important. They are important only because, and to the extent, having those virtues enables or constitutes one's contribution to the magnificent web of being.

So although there are resonances with the more pluralistic forms of consequentialism, and virtue ethics, and role ethics, and even deontology (trivially or degenerately, if the rule is just "harmonize with the dao"), the classical Chinese ethical ideal of harmonizing with the dao differs somewhat from all of these familiar (to professional philosophers) Western ethical approaches.

Many of these other approaches also contain an implicit intellectualism or elitism, in which ideal ethical goodness requires intellectual attainment: wisdom, or a sophisticated ability to weigh consequences or evaluate and apply rules -- far beyond, for example, the capacities of someone with severe cognitive disabilities. With enough Zhuangzi in the mix, such elitism evaporates. A severely cognitively disabled person, or a magnificently weird nonhuman animal, might far exceed any ordinary adult philosopher in their capacity to harmonize with the dao and might contribute more to the rich tapestry of the world.

Perhaps an ethics of harmonizing with the dao can resonate with some 21st-century Anglophone readers, despite its origins in ancient China. It is not, I think, as alien as it might seem from its reliance on the concept of dao and its failure to fit into the standard ethical triumvirate of consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics. The fundamental idea should be attractive to some: We each contribute by instantiating a unique piece of a magnificent world, a world which would be less magnificent without us.

12 comments:

Arnold said...

At "role ethics" found: "Critical discursive psychology and relational ethics"...
..."An uneasy tension?"...
By Linda M. McMullen...at "Social and Personality Psychology Compass"

My question...have you found west ways (do-no-harm-practitioners) to be off balance, by not including in relationships they themselves, as is supposed in the east...

And would you say 'something' of the invisible relationships between master and student...in the east...

I ran this by Gemini AI, in a word, east west ways are "therapeutic"...
...Is it still true, in these times, everything I need is right in front of me...
...

Matthew Hammerton said...

If you buy the argument I give here then asking whether this ethical outlook is a form of consequentialism, deontology, or virtue ethics, is not a very helpful question. It is much more useful to ask whether it is agent-neutral or agent-relative, whether it always permits maximizing the good, and what priority relations it postulates between the different moral properties it includes. I'm curious to know what answers you would give to these questions.

Matthew Hammerton said...

The link I posted didn't show up in the comment, but the arguments I was referring to are the arguments I give in "The Fundamental Divisions in Ethics" published in Inquiry a few years ago. https://philpapers.org/go.pl?aid=HAMTFD-2

Paul D. Van Pelt said...

*Theraputic* is good. From the little I know of AI and the rest of the new, wunderkind technology, and the comparatively little I know of Eastern thought, a "not doing" approach seems to hold well, philosophically. Another descriptor comes to mind, as well. That term is contemplative. Whether AI and the rest get the contemplative piece I really couldn't say with certainty. My previous administrative law chums might say something like, "it depends". Depends on what? Maybe yes, maybe no.Possibly better, then: Depends on who is interpreting what the AI tools are saying, and, what level of knowledge/understanding those tools command. I like Eastern thought, but not because I am lazy. I like to think I still place value on wisdom, over technological expertise. That does not necessarily *sit well* with modern thinkers.

Jenelle Salisbury said...

I like your characterization of Zhuangzi in terms of "wildness." I also liked your sentence - "One can be easygoing and open-minded, welcome surprise and difference, not insist on jamming everything into preconceived frames and plans; and one can contribute to the delightful weirdness of the world in one's own unique way."

Myself I've considered that Zhuangzi could inspire an ethic of care. When I read Zhuangzi I think about distinction making as activity (a la cook Ding), wherein the goal is not to make the "best" distinctions (because the dao contains none) but to make them in the best, most skillful way in a moment. This metaphysical framing about boundaries can connect to an ethic if we consider the self-other distinction to be just as provisional as any other shi fei. I do think that there is room in his framework to conceive of greater perspectival "openness" as epistemic and potentially moral growth.

Paul D. Van Pelt said...

Very good! Tasteful altruism, I think. I liked the lightness of another blog today, concerning a monkey's chance of writing Shakespeare. Some thinkers had already dismissed that notion as something like aimless mindwandering. Works for me! Best Wishes.

Paul D. Van Pelt said...

*..to everything, turn, turn, turn; there is a season, turn, turn, turn, and time to every purpose, under heaven...* Sound familiar? You were, I think, a tadpole. I had already left the pond. Things come, go, and, sometimes, return. The Arrow of Time, see. Ineffable, while being, at once, the fair witness Hofstadter and Dennett were right, which is how I came to jump out of the system...Contextualize reality, etc. Time is relative, but, as the fair witness, it cannot care.

Eric Schwitzgebel said...

Thanks for the comments, folks!

Arnold: I do think there's a risk of oversimplifying traditions when one characterizes Eastern philosophy as like *this* and Western philosophy as like *that*.

Matthew: Thanks for the link and the suggestion! Those questions are pretty abstractly formulated, so I'm not sure *exactly* what you're asking, but my guess is (1.) agent relative, (2.) sometimes maximizing the good is not permitted, and (3.) the priority will be on harmonizing with the dao. (This third claim would definitely not be shared by all, or maybe most, interpreters of Xunzi.)

Thanks for the kind words, Jenelle! It's interesting to consider what in the Inner Chapters might be used to support a caretaking attitude toward others, since the support is not visible on the surface, and yet Zhuangzi comes across as humane and caring overall. Yes, thinking of the shi-fei of self vs other as being only one limited perspective seems like one angle into that.

Paul: Yes, I think Zhuangzi would be very down with wisdom over technology and with "turn, turn, turn".

The_Virtual_Social_Worker said...

I wrote on Twitter about The Weirdness of the World, that this book is one of the most beautiful love letters to philosophy i have ever read.

One of the reasons is the way you wrote about how enriching it can be to not know every answer, to open a new space of possibilities by asking a new question. That we can find this questions everywhere, literally in our backyard, like when we see snails and ask ourselves if they are conscious.

I really enjoy this spirit of openness and curiosity in the book. It is surprisingly rare to find in humanity these days. This blogpost is another great opportunity to say thank you.

I am not interested in philosophy as an academic, i studied it a few years but quitted to become a social worker (Thank you Camus), but philosophy bothers me, i can’t really stop reading philosophy whenever i find enough time. Philosophy for me helps keeping the wonder alive. I don’t seek definitive answers, i just want to stay interested and curious and ultimately i think this leads to happiness.

There are not so many philosophers that regularly make you smile when reading them, smile not because something is funny, but because something you read suddenly opens the mind for a little bit of love for the wild and crazy world out there, for the admiration of the beauty and the weirdness.

This article made me smile in that way and i really appreciate that.

Eric Schwitzgebel said...

Aw, how sweet of you to say! Thank you for the kind words and encouragment.

Paul D. Van Pelt said...

There seems to be emergent emphasis on matters of reason, meaning and purpose. Or, RE-emergent emphasis? Those attributes/notions are ancient. Dennett claimed we had to learn from our mistakes. I don't recall his counsel, if any, on not making foolish ones. He must have said something?
One of my guiding principles, has been: do the best you can, with what you have and know: try harder to think better...My grandfather, born in 1881, put this more tersely: you DO with what you GOT. The essence is generational, as are the questions about what we ought to do. Pragmatically speaking, were we not curious, we should all be dead by now. So, Granddad's reasoning was personal, based on limitations.

Even so, I am fairly certain there are mistakes we could have averted by trying harder; thinking better, and so on...Damned be Murphy, anyhow. And, the Arrow of Time, not so fair a witness, after all.

Eric Schwitzgebel said...

Your grandpa was right!